Is it OK to Punch a Nazi? – NHSEB 2019-2020 Regional Case 13

For HSEBowlers with regionals this weekend or next, here’s a thoughtful guest analysis on case 13 from our friend Michael Andersen in Washington state. Enjoy!

Spencer, the gentleman in the case, receiving said punch.

First, it’s important to realize that this is one of those very complex topics that you would be hard-pressed to research exhaustively with a full year of prep for Ethics Bowl; nor could you adequately cover all the relevant and significant bases that need addressing in a six-minute presentation.  So, I suggest that you focus on the strongest points for your presentation or commentary, and try to relax about all the other things that “could be said.” You simply don’t have time or energy to thoroughly research all the relevant perspectives involved. Because this is such a complicated topic, I have chosen to explore in this case analysis come of the more interesting (in my view) arguments on this case’s Study Questions.  Note that it’s not exhaustive!

Secondly, a note about my own biases here.  Having just recently organized and delivered a presentation series at the Fort Vancouver Regional Library on the topic of “Defining and Responding to Hate Speech,” together with the organization in which my wife and I are active volunteers (Circle of Peace), I have been steeped in research related to this case for the past eight months.  So, it’s no surprise where my own sympathies lie. To be honest, personally I can see no defensible justification for using violence (of the “it’s okay to punch a Nazi” variety) to suppress speech or to intimidate people, even if they are actively–but otherwise non-violently–trying to advocate for bigotry and systemic discrimination against or segregation of “vulnerable populations” (i.e., ethnic minorities, LGBTQ folks, etc.).  There are arguments for government regulation of so-called “dangerous speech” that I am sympathetic to, that would effectively limited where, when and to whom proponents of discriminatory or bigoted expression can spread their message (and still protect a healthy version of First Amendment rights).  If you’re curious, slides # 50-55 of our first presentation outline some of the better arguments of this view.  However, in general, I personally am a strong free speech supporter, and, it’s worth noting, this limited censorship argument noted above would not condone or protect suppression of speech or intimidation of people as the proponents of “Nazi-punching” seem bent on.  That said, the resource handout from our first presentation will point you to a list of good online resources for further learning on this topic.

Along with cases #10 “Belief vs. Action” and #5 “Old-Fashioned Grandparents,” case #13 “Is It Okay to Punch a Nazi?” asks us to think hard about our own moral character in response to a possible (or actual) situation we may find ourselves in.  To some extent, all thorny ethical dilemmas ask this of us, but the circumstances of some cases seem to bring out this dimension of moral character for the witnesses to, or participants in, the dilemma. The question What kind of person do I want to be? stands out in bold for this case.  

For example, in this case, it may seem expedient to punch a person who appears to sympathize with Neo-Nazi beliefs, in order to broadcast a “You are not welcome here!” message to that person and to other would-be racist sympathizers.  In an age ripe with memes on social media, where a witty comeback or outlandish action can garner thousands, if not millions, of views and likes, it may seem especially tempting in the moment to be the center of attention–if only to bask in the “glory” of our “15 minutes of fame.”  However, a bit more sober reflection should reveal that such a short-lived payoff is likely to feel hollow in the long run, especially when it involves you committing acts of violence that will probably result in painful, even harsh, consequences–like the prospect of violent revenge or criminal charges.  Is sending what you deem to be an important message on social media really worth being convicted of aggravated assault? Can this really be called “civil disobedience”?

Perhaps the most long-lasting consequence for those who endorse the view that “violence is sometimes a justifiable response to political views that one disagrees with or finds objectionable” (as Study Q#1 asks us) is the effect such choices might have on our personality.  Social psychologists have long documented how “[e]xposure to violence increases aggression through reinforcement, through modeling, by priming cognitions related to aggression, and through desensitization.”  Dr. Charles Sanger, Professor of Psychology at the University of Maryland, summarizes the research on how viewing or participating in violent acts in a social situation influences a later tendency toward aggression:

“…[C]ontinually viewing violence substantially changes how we think about and how our brains respond to the events that occur to us (Bartholow, Bushman, & Sestir, 2006). Frequent exposure to violence primes aggression and makes aggressive behavior more likely (Molitor & Hirsch, 1994). And viewing aggression frequently makes that aggression seem more normal and less negative. If we create for ourselves a world that contains a lot of violence, we become more distrustful and more likely to behave aggressively in response to conflict (Nabi & Sullivan, 2001).”

Of course, a more poetic and influential authority on this point is Martin Luther King, who wrote in 1967, in the midst of the Civil Rights Movement, “Returning violence for violence multiplies violence, adding deeper darkness to a night already devoid of stars. Darkness cannot drive out darkness; only light can do that. Hate cannot drive out hate; only love can do that.”  …What kind of person do I want to be?  Surely, most of us want to be known–to ourselves and to others–by our capacity for love than for exercising our primal instincts for intimidation and violence (however righteous the language we try to dress it in).  If we agree with Aristotle that acting morally is a matter of habit, then we should investigate how to habitually act with loving-kindness rather than habituate more violent tendencies.  I concluded from my own investigation that the scientific research and the best wisdom traditions appear to echo this insight.  I encourage you to explore the topic on your own, even after Ethics Bowl concludes.

Beyond negative consequences for oneself, consider the likely negative consequences for our society more broadly if we sanction anti-racist vigilante violence.  By personally contributing to a trend of combating racism with violence, one will likely further normalize the unfortunate stereotype, “In America, we are a society that chooses violence to solve our problems.”  Boston Globe columnist Cathy Young articulated what’s at stake for us as Americans in her 2017 op-ed piece responding to a “nazi-punching” incident in Seattle:

“YET ANOTHER Nazi-punching video is making the rounds on the Internet, to cheers from quite a few people on the left.  The clip, shot in Seattle, shows a man in a swastika armband getting knocked down with a punch to the face as he tries to talk to the assailant.  Using violence to stop someone who espouses a violent ideology, many say, is legitimate self-defense. The man in the clip may or may not have been acting aggressively before the start of the video.  It’s also unclear whether he is an actual neo-Nazi or simply mentally ill.

Regardless, both the video and the applause for it on social media are disturbing signs of the times.  ‘Well done, Seattle. A+,’ went a typical comment. Another tweeter, a writer with 23,600 followers, declared, ‘Yes, I enjoyed video of the Seattle Nazi [getting] punched in the face.  Very much. Freedom of speech is not freedom from consequences.’ 

Twitter talk is cheap.  But such gleeful casual endorsements of violence are still worrisome, especially in light of what’s happening in the offline world.  One can feel no sympathy for Nazis and still realize that approval of Nazi-punching is likely to lead to escalation of political violence across the board.”

The are many recent examples of influential counter-arguments against the “It’s okay to punch a Nazi” stance–more than can be adequately explored here.  However, a few come to mind:

  • One of the aims of The Dangerous Speech Project is to share the latest research on effective strategies for anti-racist counterspeech.  They summarize the following tips (among many) for confronting particular instances of “hate speech” or against persons advocating bigotry in public:
    • Remind yourself that behind each comment–no matter how hateful–is a human being.  Treat them as you want to be treated.
    • Don’t be hostile, insulting, or aggressive–it can escalate the conflict.
  • The Southern Poverty Law Center, which has tracked hate crimes since 1971, recommends in their publication Ten Ways to Fight Hate: A Community Response Guide several time-tested alternative ways to engage publicly with those who appear to be advocates of hateful agendas espousing bigotry and discrimination:
    • “Speak up. Goodness has a First Amendment right, too. [But] Do not debate hate group members in conflict-driven forums. Instead, speak up in ways that draw attention away from hate, toward unity.
    • Create an Alternative: Do not attend a hate rally. Find another outlet for anger and frustration and for people’s desire to do something.  Hold a unity rally or parade to draw media attention away from hate.”

Regarding Study Q #2 and the prospects of “making racists afraid,” Jonathan Haidt and George Lukianoff, in their 2018 book Coddling of the American Mind: How Good Intentions and Bad Ideas Are Setting Up a Generation for Failure, examine in some depth the alarming growth in recent years of the tendency among self-identified “anti-racists” to suppress expression and justify violence on college campuses and in public forums against sources of so-called “hate speech.”  In their fourth chapter called “Intimidation and Violence,” Haidt and Lukianoff lay out an argument against justifications for this trend. Two supporting points include:

  • “In 2017, the idea that speech can be violence (even when it does not involve threats, harassment, or calls for violence) seemed to spread, assisted by the tendency in some circles to focus only on perceived impact, not on intent.  Words that give rise to stress or fear for members of some groups are now often regarded as a form of violence.
  • [But] Speech is not violence.  Treating it as such is an interpretive choice, and it is a choice that increases pain and suffering while preventing other, more effective responses, including the Stoic response (cultivating nonreactivity) and the antifragile response suggested by [progressive activist] Van Jones: ‘Put on some boots, and learn how to deal with adversity.’”

Certainly, there are some racists out there who are so fixated on their narratives of racial purity and perceived victimhood that rational discussion may seem futile.  However, it’s worth exploring whether you think it follows from these facts that our only recourse is preemptive violence against them. On a related side note, the situation outlined in the case, and the text of Study Qs #1 and #2, preclude us from equating these kind of anti-racist confrontations with our war efforts against Nazi Germany in WWII.  In the latter circumstance, Hitler and his armies invaded our allies’ lands, systematically looted them, and undertook a campaign of genocide against Jews and other political prisoners, violating human rights and committing war crimes on a mass scale. Unless you were a complete pacifist, at the time it was difficult to argue against our justifications to go to war against Hitler and his Axis partners. (…Of course, we weren’t exactly angels in our own conduct of the war, as any black American soldier in our segregated army would tell you. …But that’s another story.)  Confronted with the opportunity to “punch a Nazi” (presuming that you had reliable knowledge of his/her Neo-Nazi beliefs), you are not facing an invading army, nor are you dealing with clear threats of violence against you.  So, to equate the two justifications for violence might open you to a false equivalence fallacy charge.

In the situation described in case #13, both sides of the argument appear to agree that “[s]uch violence, in contrast, seems to be incompatible with treating someone else as a fellow citizen.”  Moreover, it’s relevant that Richard Spencer, the target of the attack, viewed that a line of basic respect had been crossed with the punch: “‘But punching like that just crosses a line—totally unacceptable.’ He admitted that he feared future attacks, saying, ‘Certainly, some people think I’m not a human being and I can just be attacked at will.’”  You could try to argue that preemptive attacks on characters like Spencer are necessary, because he (and advocates of systematic racism like him) are being hypocritical–because their message seems to justify violence against their targets. Furthermore, they are benefitting from the public peace maintained by civil society but would themselves violate it if they came into power.  Even if this charge of hypocrisy for a particular person could be definitively established, think about whether that alone justifies the preemptive attack.

This junction in the argument takes us back to Haidt and Lukianoff’s point above: that “speech is not violence,” and that a civil society must tolerate freedom of expression so long as it doesn’t violate the First Amendment limits set by rulings of the U.S. Supreme Court (or the equivalent in international law).  One key danger of equating speech with violence, argue scholars like Haidt and Lukianoff, is that campaigns to suppress so-called “hate speech” can backfire on those who are usually targets of such hateful speech. [If you need further clarification on this point, Nadine Strossen, Professor of Law at New York Law School and author of HATE: Why We Should Resist It with Free Speech, Not Censorship, outlines in this short (5:02) video what is at stake for this “hate speech”/free speech debate: “Should Hate Speech Be Censored?” The Federalist Society: POLICYbrief. For a counter perspective on this point (but one that falls short of justifying preemptive, vigilante attacks against racists like Richard Spencer), Must We Defend Nazis: Why the First Amendment Should Not Protect Hate Speech and White Supremacy, by Richard Delgado and Jean Stefancic, lays out the case that stricter counter-measures against so-called “hate speech” are justified by the damage such speech does to its targets.  In a 2017 interview about their book, Delgado and Stefancic said, “Our answer to the question, does defending Nazis really strengthen the system of free speech is, then, generally, no. Sometimes defending Nazis is simply defending Nazis.”]  

The heart of the legal debate briefly outlined above seems to be about whether censoring hateful or discriminatory speech through stricter regulations actually creates more problems than it solves.  By extension, the proponents of the “It’s okay to punch a Nazi” view seek to piggyback on the logic of the pro-censorship legal case and make it morally permissable (perhaps even legally too) to allow preemptive violence against racists like Spencer in order to induce fear and silence among them and their sympathizers.  (How exactly anti-racist individuals on the street would correctly identify and justly discern which so-called racists deserve this preemptive violence in practice is an obvious question that needs answering.) Furthermore, if it’s morally permissible to act this way in public, presumably it would be legal too; but how would authorities–police, lawyers, judges, even benevolent bystanders–manage to interpret such a law in reality, with all of the messy details such encounters are likely to involve?  Your job is to decide how closely the moral justifications track the legal arguments on either side, and to determine if morally we’re collectively better off by sanctioning preemptive violence against apparently dangerous racists–even when they are not acting violently themselves.  

As part of our third session of the FVRL series on Hate Speech, we summarized some of the powerful insights about how to effectively express solidarity or support for those who oppose or are affected by bigotry.  You can find some good resources in the session handout about this, and particularly in the recent Discovery Channel series Why We Hate, co-produced by Steven Spielberg (scroll down for the trailer).  To help you answer Study Q #3, the slides and speaker notes from that presentation summarize a few of the key points from this documentary series, as well as other insights from experts who have worked with targets of racism.

Finally, to echo a message we coaches have always tried to reinforce, we want you to think for yourselves on this and any Ethics Bowl case.  It’s not our job to tell you what to think. The perspectives I outlined here are undoubtedly biased by my personal outlook on free speech and violence.  As we attempted to do in our presentations at the FVRL, I have tried here to fairly represent the perspectives involved. It’s for you to decide how successful my attempts at an unbiased case evaluation actually were.  Good luck on Saturday!

Leave a Reply