This week our friends at the Parr Center announced a virtual ethics bowl celebration scheduled for mid-June – the 2020 Ethics Bowl Summit.
“[T]he NHSEB invites you to join in a review, recognition, and celebration of some of the extraordinary things our community has accomplished this year! The 2020 Ethics Bowl Summit is scheduled for 7pm (ET) on the evening of [Saturday] June 13, 2020 and will feature exciting updates and developments from NHSEB leadership, perspectives from students, coaches, and organizers across the U.S., and, of course, recognition of our regional winners, case competition winners, national finalist teams, and more!”
The event will be viewable via live stream on YouTube and on the NHSEB’s social medial platforms. Full information will be posted at NHSEBonline.org. So mark your calendar, and hope to see you there (online).
Organizers of the Michigan High School Ethics Bowl invite you to write a COVID-themed case for the 2020-2021 season.
Art by Raphael. Captions by A2Ethics.
From an email distributed by A2Ethics late May, “There are so many ethical dilemmas we are witnessing and going through… [W]e urge you to include the moral dimensions of what is happening. Or not happening… to broaden and embolden your diary and journal-keeping by: Writing an ethics case study for the 2021 Michigan High School Ethics Bowl. Now is a perfect time to practice risky thinking–during a time of extreme risk. What political philosopher Hannah Arendt calls ‘thinking without a banister.’”
And don’t be shy! Maybe you’ve never written a case before. Maybe your case won’t be selected. But simply giving it a shot will make you a better writer, a better bowler, and probably a braver, more action-oriented person. Somebody’s case has to be chosen. Why not yours?
This past Tuesday evening, having grown bored of Adam Sandler’s Uncut Gems (Waterboy is more my style), I decided to call it a night around 11:30. Checking my email one last time, I saw a message from Ethics Olympiad director Matthew Wills from 9:55: “The Olympiad is beginning…”
I was confused. I’d been honored to be invited to serve as a judge for the online event. But it was scheduled for the following evening – Wednesday, May 27th at 10 p.m. Tennessee time, which would be 11 a.m. in Perth. My error became apparent when I realized that while it was still Tuesday, May 26th in Tennessee, it was in fact already Wednesday, May 27th in Australia…
I sent a quick apology, and wrestled with whether to hide or log on. My better side won the debate and I quickly joined the Zoom meeting (not taking time to change out of my blue jammies) to see if there was anything I might be able to do, and if nothing else, to apologize via video.
Matthew was all smiles and graciousness, per usual – not the nervous wreck that organizers sometimes devolve into, especially when their judges flake out…
Smartly, he’d pre-recruited a backup, just in case, and everything was progressing as planned. He asked if I’d like to sit in on one of the heats in a Zoom break-out room.
Surreal seeing the sun shining when it’s near midnight(!). Yay, technology.
It was for a match between Santa Sabina College and St. Peters Girls Academy. The teams were together at their respective schools, judges Rosalind Walsh and Jennifer Duke-Wonge appeared to be in their offices, and so too was moderator Theo Stapleton.
Considering the NHSEB case, “Is it OK to Punch a Nazi?” the teams were both well-prepared, and quick on their feet. They were respectful and engaged, and did a nice job sharing the floor, taking turns to elaborate on and clarify their arguments. The judges asked excellent questions (homing in on key aspects of the teams’ positions, but doing so in a friendly way), and Theo did an expert job keeping everyone on track – a wonderful balance of professionalism and warmth.
Zoom proved a superb platform. The video quality was great, and as far as I could tell, hardly glitched at all. My own connection was via a smartphone hotspot, which I worried might not be able to keep up. But it did without issue, and so did everyone else’s – a mini miracle I’m still impressed to witness.
The result of the event, which featured 8 teams from 8 different schools, was that St Peters Girls Adelaide, Santa Sabina College Sydney and The Kings School Sydney advanced to participate in the China Australia Ethics Olympiad on June 25th. Congrats to all three, and to the other teams who were all very close in the final scores.
Kudos to Matthew for doing such a nice job with the event. The participants appeared to enjoy themselves and grow from the experience. And this COVID-driven transition to online Ethics Olympiads (and Bowls) will no doubt continue to expand opportunities for international collaboration. There’s something reassuring about seeing teams on the other side of the globe (made apparent by the fact that it’s midnight where I am, yet I can see sunlight out the classroom window behind a team) think through cases addressed next door. There’s also something special about how Australians can say “cheers” with such authenticity…
And if you yourself are invited to participate in an international Ethics Olympiad, pay special attention to not only the local time, but the date. Don’t get sucked into bad movies on Netflix. And maybe be on standby the day before and after with a polo and sports jacket, just in case.
Last week National High School Ethics Bowl Director Alex Richardson shared the following with regional organizers. Reprinted here in full (with complementary video) Alex outlines the move of NHSEB online, includes links to several engaging resources, and (unless I’m misreading – have messaged Alex to confirm) expands inclusion beyond winners of the regional bowls to all NHSEB participants(!). May 8th UPDATE: Alex confirmed — the new online resources are open to all NHSEB Regional participants! Kudos to UNC for making these changes to sustain (and grow!) ethics bowl during this challenging age of COVID.
I hope you are all staying safe and healthy during what is shaping up to be a challenging time for us all.
My team at the Parr Center and I have been working hard in the past few weeks to bring parts of the NHSEB experience online in the wake of the cancellation of our National Competition due to COVID-19. Today, I’m thrilled to introduce you to NHSEBOnline, a new slate of programming to engage our students virtually and keep up the conversations that make our activity what it is.
The program will include three central initiatives: (1) asynchronous online Discussion Threads which allow students to engage each other in conversation about an abridged Case Set via video, audio, and text-based messaging, (2) weekly Group “Huddles” where students can discuss problems and prospects with NHSEB staff and volunteer organizers via videoconference, and finally (3) a virtual Ethics Bowl Summit in late May which will bring together students, organizers, volunteers, and parents from across the country to recognize and feature our National Finalists, celebrate with all of our students, and close out the 2019-2020 season! More information about format and scheduling for the Summit will be released in the coming weeks. I hope you’ll share this message and the video above with your coaches and students. Registration for participants is now open. We are also continually looking for volunteer organizers to help out with the administration of the program and planning for the end of the year. Your help is most welcome! Conversation is the essence of this activity, and I’m so excited to see it continue, particularly during the complex and challenging times we find ourselves in.
I hope you’ll join us in this experiment, and encourage your students and coaches to do the same.
Alex Richardson, Director, National High School Ethics Bowl, Parr Center for Ethics, UNC Chapel Hill
Our Ethics Olympiad friends in Australia are proving fast to respond to the COVID crisis, both in sustaining ethics bowl in the online environment, and in tackling virus-related ethical issues sooner rather than later.
Screen shot from the recent China/Australia Ethics Olympiad “friendly”
If you’re unfamiliar, Ethics Olympiad is very much like Ethics Bowl, and in fact often leverages U.S. ethics bowl cases. Founder Matthew Wills and team have been in the ethics bowl game for several years now. In fact, he soldiered through a very long flight to attend the very first National High School Ethics Bowl at UNC, and he and I co-hosted a virtual bowl around 2011 with teams from Tennessee, California, and Perth (Australia).
In an email update sent earlier this week, Matthew shared the results of a recent China/Australia online high school Ethics Olympiad friendly, upcoming ethics teaching and bowl coaching professional development online sessions scheduled for May, an invite to the Middle School Ethics Olympiad scheduled for November, as well as some COVID-19 ethical questions including “How should governments weigh violations of individual liberties against protecting the health and well-being of others during a health crisis?” – a tough one for sure, and something I’m certain our teams will have superb insights on. Feel free and encouraged to share yours in a comment below. P.S. Thank you for not killing Tom Hanks.
Participation in Ethics Olympiad, which requires registration, is open to schools everywhere. In addition to bonus teaching resources, members enjoy the ability to remotely compete with teams from North Carolina to Western Australia, New Zealand to the UK, Tasmania to Texas. School membership is $180 the first year, then $80 annually thereafter – click here or reach out to admin@ethicsolympiad.org for more information, and kudos to our friends down under for continuing to fight the good fight during this difficult time.
With COVID-19 causing ethics bowl cancellations, school disruptions, and generally throwing a wrench into life as we know it, here’s a 10-minute tip vid on how to teach philosophy online. If you have your own ideas (especially ethics-bowl specific stuff), please share — would love to put together a post on how to coach/practice/continue ethics bowl online.
This virus will pass. In the meantime, stay strong! The world will continue to need ethics bowl as a beacon of civility and thoughtfulness (as this crisis is proving). You’re as much a part of that as anyone, so wash those hands 🙂
The NHSEB case-writing team deserves kudos for all the
cases, but I especially enjoyed case #7. It enriched and challenged my understanding,
and left me undecided on the issue even 24 hours after first reading it. Let’s
see if I can make some sense of my conflicting intuitions.
Case 7 asks us to consider the ethics of outside influence
in domestic political decisions, and offers three examples:
Foreign activists influencing the 2018
referendum on Ireland’s constitutional abortion ban
Civil rights activists (often from areas of the
country outside of the South) advocating for desegregation and racial equality
during the 1960s
Russian-funded political ads which influenced
the 2016 American presidential election
On the one hand, maybe the result is what’s most
important. If we think that overturning Ireland’s abortion ban was morally
best, the progress of the Civil Rights movement was morally best, and the outcome
of the 2016 election was morally best, then we might welcome outside influence.
On the other hand, maybe we want each country’s citizens to
make their own political decisions. Part of the allure of democracy is that it
allows people to self-govern through the collective consideration and
endorsement of laws. But to the extent that the legislative and voting process
is manipulated by outsiders, the result doesn’t reflect the untainted views of the
citizenry.
With the Civil Rights movement, one could argue (and the case
alludes to the fact) that while Freedom Riders often weren’t from segregationist
states, they were citizens of the United States, and since civil rights was
a federal issue, their influence wasn’t external after all, or at least not as
external as Americans influencing Ireland’s abortion policies, or Russians
influencing America’s presidency.
The civil rights scenario is actually the only one with an
uncontroversial outcome, for it’s clear that humans deserve equal treatment independent
of their race. Abortion, on the other hand, is hotly contested, and so too is whether
Clinton or Trump were better suited to be America’s president. Therefore, it might
be best to set aside the abortion and presidency cases and focus on the Civil
Rights activists, or to (possibly even better) consider a hypothetical scenario
where the morality is less controversial.
Imagine European protestors opposing Hitler. On the one hand,
we respect Germans’ interest in autonomous self-government. But on the other
hand, it’s clear that Nazi death camps are unethical – in fact so
unethical as to override our usual deference to countries’ citizens to self-govern.
In this clear case, it would seem that the outcome is more important than the
process, and therefore we’d endorse outside interference.
It’s questionable whether we’d say the same for less extreme
cases – might want to defer to a peoples’ internal judgment when equally
intelligent people reasonably disagree, as they continue to do over both
abortion and Trump v. Clinton. However, you might argue that the stakes for
abortion in Ireland and/or the presidency in the U.S. were similarly grave to
those of death camps in Germany. One pits women’s interest in being able to end
unwanted pregnancies against the value of a potential person. The other
concerns the influence of a nation’s chief executive on everything from healthcare
to Supreme Court Justice nominees to control of the world’s largest nuclear arsenal.
Those are some pretty high stakes! Arguably
high enough to allow outside interference, only though only of the right sort.
That is, whatever your current view on abortion and Trump v.
Clinton, imagine like-minded foreigners working to move American politics in
that direction. When the outside support is on your side, it doesn’t seem as
objectionable, does it? Or are your own intuitions driving you to defer instead
to the integrity of the democratic process? I remain conflicted… But then when
I consider outside protestors opposing Hitler, return to the tentative view
that when the stakes are high enough, outside intervention is OK.
Teams, you have the luxury of a group of intelligent
teammates and coaches – hoping these initial thoughts will spur good
discussion. Should you figure this out, please share in a comment below – I need
the help 🙂 Cheers, Matt
Nandi’s child would be older, but still, a beautiful family (courtesy the Baby Center India)
Case #5 in the 2020 Nationals case pool concerns a newlywed Indian
named Nandi. Nandi and his wife get some big news: #1 they’re pregnant. #2
Nandi “has received a scholarship to pursue a college education at a prestigious
university in the United States.” They decide to move, but promise their
families they will return once Nandi has earned his Bachelor’s.
Nandi not only earns his Bachelor’s, but is offered entry
into an impressive Ph.D. program “with the promise of full funding and the prospect
of a successful and lucrative career.” He accepts, and after 7 years away from
home, receives word that his father has died.
Per Indian tradition, since Nandi is the eldest son, he is expected
to welcome his widowed mother into his home and care for her for the duration
of her life. However, his mother is unwilling to move to the U.S. (which would
require her to leave Nandi’s four sisters), and reminds Nandi of his promise to
return to India after earning his Bachelor’s.
At its core, this case pits personal ambition and family
betterment against broader familial obligations and the binding power of
promise. Can a win-win compromise be achieved? And if one can’t, which decision
is all-things-considered most ethical?
The second study question is a good one, asking, “What are
the relevant factors Nandi should consider when making his decision?” Factors
to entertain would include:
The impact on Nandi’s mother. Depending on his
choice, how emotionally harmed is she likely to be? How severely would
finishing his Ph.D. before returning to India damage their relationship? (With transparent
discussion, could she respect his decision and be reassured, or would anything
short of immediate and permanent return be perceived as an unforgivable
betrayal?) Would she be able to live comfortably without him short-term? (For
example, if she’d become immediately homeless and starve, this would be reason
to return now. If she’d be materially secure and emotionally supported by her
daughters while Nandi completed his schooling, this would lighten the moral scales
on that side.)
The impact on Nandi’s wife. The case doesn’t mention
Nandi’s wife’s preferences or interests. Would she prefer to live in the U.S.
or India? Is she pursuing her own education or career? Does she miss or have additional
obligations to her own family? Is her delayed return to India causing grief
with her own parents?
The impact on Nandi’s child. Nandi’s child currently
isn’t able to visit aunts, uncles, cousins or grandparents. The child is also
growing up immersed in American rather than Indian culture (maybe a bad thing,
maybe a good thing – those who know more about Indian culture than I do will
have to decide). What’s the general quality of life – safety, educational
opportunities, recreation – where they’ve been living in the U.S. vs. where
they would be living in India? Does the child have strong friendships?
The time remaining in his Ph.D. studies. If only a
few months, this would mitigate some of the negative impacts of continuing his
studies in the U.S.
The nature and potential impact of his studies. The
case details don’t clarify what Nandi’s Ph.D. is in. Nuclear medicine or basket
weaving? Sustainable tech or bowling? To the extent that Nandi’s studies have a
real potential to substantially better mankind, this would weight the scales in
favor of continuing his studies.
Possible win-win solutions. Might Nandi be able to complete
the remainder of his doctorate long-distance with a handful of quick trips to
the U.S., or possibly transfer to a school in India? Depending on her age and
health, might Nandi return to India, focus on caring for his mother for now,
and then return to the U.S. and finish his studies upon her death?
Win-wins are definitely a good thing in the real world. However,
as any team advancing to the nationals knows, ethics bowl cases are
intentionally written to pit conflicting considerations against one another, to
force teams to make and explain principled decisions. So while it doesn’t hurt
to have a few dilemma-resolving solutions in your back pocket, know that judges
expect teams to be able to make tough calls, and are likely to change the details
to force teams to make a principled decision. For example, “That’s great, but
assume Nandi can’t pursue his doctorate long-distance? Which considerations
would win in that case and why?”
For HSEBowlers with regionals this weekend or next, here’s a thoughtful guest analysis on case 13 from our friend Michael Andersen in Washington state. Enjoy!
Spencer, the gentleman in the case, receiving said punch.
First, it’s important to realize that this is one of those very complex topics that you would be hard-pressed to research exhaustively with a full year of prep for Ethics Bowl; nor could you adequately cover all the relevant and significant bases that need addressing in a six-minute presentation. So, I suggest that you focus on the strongest points for your presentation or commentary, and try to relax about all the other things that “could be said.” You simply don’t have time or energy to thoroughly research all the relevant perspectives involved. Because this is such a complicated topic, I have chosen to explore in this case analysis come of the more interesting (in my view) arguments on this case’s Study Questions. Note that it’s not exhaustive!
Secondly, a note about my own biases here. Having just recently organized and delivered a presentation series at the Fort Vancouver Regional Library on the topic of “Defining and Responding to Hate Speech,” together with the organization in which my wife and I are active volunteers (Circle of Peace), I have been steeped in research related to this case for the past eight months. So, it’s no surprise where my own sympathies lie. To be honest, personally I can see no defensible justification for using violence (of the “it’s okay to punch a Nazi” variety) to suppress speech or to intimidate people, even if they are actively–but otherwise non-violently–trying to advocate for bigotry and systemic discrimination against or segregation of “vulnerable populations” (i.e., ethnic minorities, LGBTQ folks, etc.). There are arguments for government regulation of so-called “dangerous speech” that I am sympathetic to, that would effectively limited where, when and to whom proponents of discriminatory or bigoted expression can spread their message (and still protect a healthy version of First Amendment rights). If you’re curious, slides # 50-55 of our first presentation outline some of the better arguments of this view. However, in general, I personally am a strong free speech supporter, and, it’s worth noting, this limited censorship argument noted above would not condone or protect suppression of speech or intimidation of people as the proponents of “Nazi-punching” seem bent on. That said, the resource handout from our first presentation will point you to a list of good online resources for further learning on this topic.
Along with cases #10 “Belief vs. Action” and #5 “Old-Fashioned Grandparents,” case #13 “Is It Okay to Punch a Nazi?” asks us to think hard about our own moral character in response to a possible (or actual) situation we may find ourselves in. To some extent, all thorny ethical dilemmas ask this of us, but the circumstances of some cases seem to bring out this dimension of moral character for the witnesses to, or participants in, the dilemma. The question What kind of person do I want to be? stands out in bold for this case.
For example, in this case, it may seem expedient to punch a person who appears to sympathize with Neo-Nazi beliefs, in order to broadcast a “You are not welcome here!” message to that person and to other would-be racist sympathizers. In an age ripe with memes on social media, where a witty comeback or outlandish action can garner thousands, if not millions, of views and likes, it may seem especially tempting in the moment to be the center of attention–if only to bask in the “glory” of our “15 minutes of fame.” However, a bit more sober reflection should reveal that such a short-lived payoff is likely to feel hollow in the long run, especially when it involves you committing acts of violence that will probably result in painful, even harsh, consequences–like the prospect of violent revenge or criminal charges. Is sending what you deem to be an important message on social media really worth being convicted of aggravated assault? Can this really be called “civil disobedience”?
Perhaps the most long-lasting consequence for those who endorse the view that “violence is sometimes a justifiable response to political views that one disagrees with or finds objectionable” (as Study Q#1 asks us) is the effect such choices might have on our personality. Social psychologists have long documented how “[e]xposure to violence increases aggression through reinforcement, through modeling, by priming cognitions related to aggression, and through desensitization.” Dr. Charles Sanger, Professor of Psychology at the University of Maryland, summarizes the research on how viewing or participating in violent acts in a social situation influences a later tendency toward aggression:
“…[C]ontinually viewing violence substantially changes how we think about and how our brains respond to the events that occur to us (Bartholow, Bushman, & Sestir, 2006). Frequent exposure to violence primes aggression and makes aggressive behavior more likely (Molitor & Hirsch, 1994). And viewing aggression frequently makes that aggression seem more normal and less negative. If we create for ourselves a world that contains a lot of violence, we become more distrustful and more likely to behave aggressively in response to conflict (Nabi & Sullivan, 2001).”
Of course, a more poetic and influential authority on this point is Martin Luther King, who wrote in 1967, in the midst of the Civil Rights Movement, “Returning violence for violence multiplies violence, adding deeper darkness to a night already devoid of stars. Darkness cannot drive out darkness; only light can do that. Hate cannot drive out hate; only love can do that.” …What kind of person do I want to be? Surely, most of us want to be known–to ourselves and to others–by our capacity for love than for exercising our primal instincts for intimidation and violence (however righteous the language we try to dress it in). If we agree with Aristotle that acting morally is a matter of habit, then we should investigate how to habitually act with loving-kindness rather than habituate more violent tendencies. I concluded from my own investigation that the scientific research and the best wisdom traditions appear to echo this insight. I encourage you to explore the topic on your own, even after Ethics Bowl concludes.
Beyond negative consequences for oneself, consider the likely negative consequences for our society more broadly if we sanction anti-racist vigilante violence. By personally contributing to a trend of combating racism with violence, one will likely further normalize the unfortunate stereotype, “In America, we are a society that chooses violence to solve our problems.” Boston Globe columnist Cathy Young articulated what’s at stake for us as Americans in her 2017 op-ed piece responding to a “nazi-punching” incident in Seattle:
“YET ANOTHER Nazi-punching video is making the rounds on the Internet, to cheers from quite a few people on the left. The clip, shot in Seattle, shows a man in a swastika armband getting knocked down with a punch to the face as he tries to talk to the assailant. Using violence to stop someone who espouses a violent ideology, many say, is legitimate self-defense. The man in the clip may or may not have been acting aggressively before the start of the video. It’s also unclear whether he is an actual neo-Nazi or simply mentally ill.
Regardless, both the video and the applause for it on social media are disturbing signs of the times. ‘Well done, Seattle. A+,’ went a typical comment. Another tweeter, a writer with 23,600 followers, declared, ‘Yes, I enjoyed video of the Seattle Nazi [getting] punched in the face. Very much. Freedom of speech is not freedom from consequences.’
Twitter talk is cheap. But such gleeful casual endorsements of violence are still worrisome, especially in light of what’s happening in the offline world. One can feel no sympathy for Nazis and still realize that approval of Nazi-punching is likely to lead to escalation of political violence across the board.”
The are many recent examples of influential counter-arguments against the “It’s okay to punch a Nazi” stance–more than can be adequately explored here. However, a few come to mind:
One of the aims of The Dangerous Speech Project is to share the latest research on effective strategies for anti-racist counterspeech. They summarize the following tips (among many) for confronting particular instances of “hate speech” or against persons advocating bigotry in public:
Remind yourself that behind each comment–no matter how hateful–is a human being. Treat them as you want to be treated.
Don’t be hostile, insulting, or aggressive–it can escalate the conflict.
The Southern Poverty Law Center, which has tracked hate crimes since 1971, recommends in their publication Ten Ways to Fight Hate: A Community Response Guide several time-tested alternative ways to engage publicly with those who appear to be advocates of hateful agendas espousing bigotry and discrimination:
“Speak up. Goodness has a First Amendment right, too. [But] Do not debate hate group members in conflict-driven forums. Instead, speak up in ways that draw attention away from hate, toward unity.
Create an Alternative: Do not attend a hate rally. Find another outlet for anger and frustration and for people’s desire to do something. Hold a unity rally or parade to draw media attention away from hate.”
Regarding Study Q #2 and the prospects of “making racists afraid,” Jonathan Haidt and George Lukianoff, in their 2018 book Coddling of the American Mind: How Good Intentions and Bad Ideas Are Setting Up a Generation for Failure, examine in some depth the alarming growth in recent years of the tendency among self-identified “anti-racists” to suppress expression and justify violence on college campuses and in public forums against sources of so-called “hate speech.” In their fourth chapter called “Intimidation and Violence,” Haidt and Lukianoff lay out an argument against justifications for this trend. Two supporting points include:
“In 2017, the idea that speech can be violence (even when it does not involve threats, harassment, or calls for violence) seemed to spread, assisted by the tendency in some circles to focus only on perceived impact, not on intent. Words that give rise to stress or fear for members of some groups are now often regarded as a form of violence.
[But] Speech is not violence. Treating it as such is an interpretive choice, and it is a choice that increases pain and suffering while preventing other, more effective responses, including the Stoic response (cultivating nonreactivity) and the antifragile response suggested by [progressive activist] Van Jones: ‘Put on some boots, and learn how to deal with adversity.’”
Certainly, there are some racists out there who are so fixated on their narratives of racial purity and perceived victimhood that rational discussion may seem futile. However, it’s worth exploring whether you think it follows from these facts that our only recourse is preemptive violence against them. On a related side note, the situation outlined in the case, and the text of Study Qs #1 and #2, preclude us from equating these kind of anti-racist confrontations with our war efforts against Nazi Germany in WWII. In the latter circumstance, Hitler and his armies invaded our allies’ lands, systematically looted them, and undertook a campaign of genocide against Jews and other political prisoners, violating human rights and committing war crimes on a mass scale. Unless you were a complete pacifist, at the time it was difficult to argue against our justifications to go to war against Hitler and his Axis partners. (…Of course, we weren’t exactly angels in our own conduct of the war, as any black American soldier in our segregated army would tell you. …But that’s another story.) Confronted with the opportunity to “punch a Nazi” (presuming that you had reliable knowledge of his/her Neo-Nazi beliefs), you are not facing an invading army, nor are you dealing with clear threats of violence against you. So, to equate the two justifications for violence might open you to a false equivalence fallacy charge.
In the situation described in case #13, both sides of the argument appear to agree that “[s]uch violence, in contrast, seems to be incompatible with treating someone else as a fellow citizen.” Moreover, it’s relevant that Richard Spencer, the target of the attack, viewed that a line of basic respect had been crossed with the punch: “‘But punching like that just crosses a line—totally unacceptable.’ He admitted that he feared future attacks, saying, ‘Certainly, some people think I’m not a human being and I can just be attacked at will.’” You could try to argue that preemptive attacks on characters like Spencer are necessary, because he (and advocates of systematic racism like him) are being hypocritical–because their message seems to justify violence against their targets. Furthermore, they are benefitting from the public peace maintained by civil society but would themselves violate it if they came into power. Even if this charge of hypocrisy for a particular person could be definitively established, think about whether that alone justifies the preemptive attack.
This junction in the argument takes us back to Haidt and Lukianoff’s point above: that “speech is not violence,” and that a civil society must tolerate freedom of expression so long as it doesn’t violate the First Amendment limits set by rulings of the U.S. Supreme Court (or the equivalent in international law). One key danger of equating speech with violence, argue scholars like Haidt and Lukianoff, is that campaigns to suppress so-called “hate speech” can backfire on those who are usually targets of such hateful speech. [If you need further clarification on this point, Nadine Strossen, Professor of Law at New York Law School and author of HATE: Why We Should Resist It with Free Speech, Not Censorship, outlines in this short (5:02) video what is at stake for this “hate speech”/free speech debate: “Should Hate Speech Be Censored?” The Federalist Society: POLICYbrief. For a counter perspective on this point (but one that falls short of justifying preemptive, vigilante attacks against racists like Richard Spencer), Must We Defend Nazis: Why the First Amendment Should Not Protect Hate Speech and White Supremacy, by Richard Delgado and Jean Stefancic, lays out the case that stricter counter-measures against so-called “hate speech” are justified by the damage such speech does to its targets. In a 2017 interview about their book, Delgado and Stefancic said, “Our answer to the question, does defending Nazis really strengthen the system of free speech is, then, generally, no. Sometimes defending Nazis is simply defending Nazis.”]
The heart of the legal debate briefly outlined above seems to be about whether censoring hateful or discriminatory speech through stricter regulations actually creates more problems than it solves. By extension, the proponents of the “It’s okay to punch a Nazi” view seek to piggyback on the logic of the pro-censorship legal case and make it morally permissable (perhaps even legally too) to allow preemptive violence against racists like Spencer in order to induce fear and silence among them and their sympathizers. (How exactly anti-racist individuals on the street would correctly identify and justly discern which so-called racists deserve this preemptive violence in practice is an obvious question that needs answering.) Furthermore, if it’s morally permissible to act this way in public, presumably it would be legal too; but how would authorities–police, lawyers, judges, even benevolent bystanders–manage to interpret such a law in reality, with all of the messy details such encounters are likely to involve? Your job is to decide how closely the moral justifications track the legal arguments on either side, and to determine if morally we’re collectively better off by sanctioning preemptive violence against apparently dangerous racists–even when they are not acting violently themselves.
As part of our third session of the FVRL series on Hate Speech, we summarized some of the powerful insights about how to effectively express solidarity or support for those who oppose or are affected by bigotry. You can find some good resources in the session handout about this, and particularly in the recent Discovery Channel series Why We Hate, co-produced by Steven Spielberg (scroll down for the trailer). To help you answer Study Q #3, the slides and speaker notes from that presentation summarize a few of the key points from this documentary series, as well as other insights from experts who have worked with targets of racism.
Finally, to echo a message we coaches have always tried to reinforce, we want you to think for yourselves on this and any Ethics Bowl case. It’s not our job to tell you what to think. The perspectives I outlined here are undoubtedly biased by my personal outlook on free speech and violence. As we attempted to do in our presentations at the FVRL, I have tried here to fairly represent the perspectives involved. It’s for you to decide how successful my attempts at an unbiased case evaluation actually were. Good luck on Saturday!
Inspired by a recent Case Summary Matrix post, Vancouver, Washington HSEB coach and regular EthicsBowl.org contributor Michael Andersen reached out to share two very nice related tools: a Case Analysis Form and a Team Organization Form.
The Case Analysis form has three columns on each of three pages, with three of the below categories on each:
Central moral dimensions in this case / values
or principles in conflict–as
related in the case description, or reasonably inferred from it
Who cares? / Different viewpoints, worldviews
engaged with this
case (i.e., stakeholders)
How do these parties appear to evaluate the
moral problem(s) of the case? (and from
what ethical framework, using what key language?)
What exactly does each stakeholder argue? List underlying premises (their reasons,
assumptions) and their conclusion. Check for valid / sound reasoning.
Most relevant fact claims that we need to research in each party’s
argument. Is their supporting evidence from reliable sources?
Most likely counter-arguments (include supporting evidence &
reasoning)
What exactly will we argue? List underlying premises (our reason and
assumptions) and our conclusion. Check
for valid / sound reasoning.
Most relevant fact claims that we need to research to support our
argument. Are our sources for this
evidence reliable?
Most likely counter-arguments we will encounter + our responses
Page 1, for example, looks like this:
Engaging prompts, inspiring the critical thought and identification of key details that make for a quality analysis. A smart approach for sure.
The idea behind the second resource, the Team Organization Form, is to proactively assign team members various responsibilities so a) they know how to concentrate during prep, and b) they can confidently operate within their realm of expertise and comfort during the bowl.
As Michael explains it, “You’ll notice that for each team member there is a split column under their name. The first side of the column is to record the role code (key at bottom) if they are the Presenting Team on a given case; the second side is to record the role code if they are the Commentary Team on a given case. Using this form, students can see on one page what their particular roles are across the array of cases assigned for the Ethics Bowl.”
“I intended this as a stress-reducer tool, as team members have fewer roles for which they are ‘on point’ for the cases (as opposed to feeling that they have to master all of the responsibilities for every case). Of course, this tool is only useful for teams that decide to divide their responsibilities such that every team member (roughly) has a role to play for all the cases encountered–as opposed to teams who split responsibilities by assigning whole cases to particular team members.” Looks like this:
Two very thoughtful and sophisticated resources — if you’d like an editable version of either, just email (matt (at) mattdeaton.com). And thanks again, Michael, for the valuable contributions! Sharing reusable tools such as these is definitely consistent with the collaborative, cooperative spirit of ethics bowl. I suspect ethics bowl creator Bob Ladenson would give you two enthusiastic thumbs up 🙂